The Sciences and Ethics 2/4

5
7453

It is in the field of the experimental sciences that we can best understand the need for
ethics to be autonomous in both senses. Ethics is inevitably bound up with the subject
who refers to it or produces it (in the case of religious or rational ethics) or with the
object to which it has to be applied (the life science, medicine: the realms of
bioethics), but must remain distinct from both the subject and the object. The subject,
in other words, puts forward his ethics as, on the one hand, a norm (or corpus of
norms) that he would like to be shared by all and, on the other, as a norm that must
never be confused with the free practice of a science as it establishes ethical and
juridical limits (whose goal is to prevent the abuse of science). No matter whether we
are speaking from within a philosophical or religious tradition, or from the point
where they interact, imposing one’s own norm is an expression of the spirit of
dogmatism and exclusivism, whereas interfering with the twofold autonomy of
science and ethics (by confusing the two realms of knowledge) can muzzle the
sciences and can let the inquisitorial spirit emerge once more.

It also has to be said that the contemporary sciences remind us every day of
the need for ethics. Scientific knowledge is now so complex and efficient that men
have the power to transform nature and the Creation, to manipulate genes and to
produce the means of their own destruction. The experiments that have been carried
out, the technologies that have been developed and the constant scientific advances
that are being made have implications for life, the intellect, collective psychology,
social relations, the natural order, the climate and, of course, the future of humanity.
Expert and scientific commissions have been established, and the number of
committees on ethics has increased dramatically: their goal is to open up a space for
collective negotiations between the agents of scientific progress and the guardians of
the human conscience who wish to prevent abuses of knowledge that might turn
against its human authors and destroy them.

There are numerous and contradictory interests involved here. Science is
indeed concerned with knowledge, but its interdependent relations with the world of
the economy make its decision-making procedures more complex. The knowledge
and progress that the sciences allow generate skills, interests and wealth. The
contemporary sciences, for instance, produce both knowledge and money, and
economic operators (who are rarely invited to sit on scientific commissions and ethics
committees) often play the part of the omnipresent but absent agent who bears upon
the atmosphere of the place and influences the direction taken by the debates and the
nature of the decisions that are taken. When so many millions of dollars and so many
private and/or public interests are at stake, realism demands that we put into
perspective the competence and powers of the committees on ethics and the calls for
collective responsibility. Declarations of good intent, scientific studies and expert
opinions notwithstanding, we have seen how little effect ethical and ecological
recommendations have when the economy and the multinationals bring all their
influence to bear on political decision-making processes. The United States’ failure to
ratify the Kyoto protocol on cutting emissions of greenhouse gases (even though it is
the most polluting country on earth) is only one of the many examples of how a
conflict of interests can arise between the domains of ethics, the sciences, the
economy and politics.

The world of the experimental sciences means that we have to think about
ethics in terms that concentrate upon its concrete application and which, to that extent,
prevent us from getting lost in nebulous and relatively unproductive preliminary
philosophical debates. Moreover, an inductive approach – one which works
backwards from the question of the practical applications of ethical norms to their
source – allows us to clarify the status of ethics at the core of the pluralism of
spiritualities, religions and philosophies on the one hand, and with respect to the
object or activity to which it is applied on the other. The principles of ethics can be
derived from what is considered to be a universal moral law (to use Kant’s
terminology), but we must all be aware that there are many different philosophies and
spiritual and religious traditions, and that we must therefore debate and exchange
different points of view and determine the status and nature of the values we share.
Those values do not belong to us alone, and nor are they the property of a religion or
philosophy that can be imposed on others. They are the common property of the
social or human community (depending on whether the question is discussed in
national or international terms). Some basic challenges call into question our ability to
produce, together, a shared universal ethics that can and must be applied, because they
are global, transnational and transcultural. That is what the theologian Hans Kung
wishes to achieve with his project for a ‘planetary ethics’ that is in keeping with
interfaith initiatives and transversal and very concrete forms of cooperation between
different traditions and religions.

Ethics is born of itself, but is independent of itself. Once it becomes a product
that is shared collectively it must also, as we have already said, become distinct from
its object if it is to ensure that, rather than forcing itself upon scientific methods, it
concentrates on the limits to their applications (whilst obviously concerning itself
with their meaning). It is imperative for it to maintain its independence from all other
domains of human activity, and above all from politics and economics. And that
independence is both its strength and its weakness. Because it is not subordinate to
any order, it can claim to be the objective norm we can use to evaluate the accurary of
human choices, be they scientific, political or economic. And yet its independence
does not give ethics any leverage that allows it to have a practical influence on the
real world or to transform behaviours. Theologians, philosophers, scientists and
ecological activists may well discuss meanings, limitations, human responsibility and
the destruction of the planet, but they often look like ineffectual dreamers. They
sometimes speak loudly, but they do not really have the means to change anything.
The power of ethics is no longer religious, philosophical or political; it lies simply –
and unfortunately – in its awareness of the imminent catastrophes that men are about
to unleash because they are so irresponsible. The power of a rational ethics stems
from the fact that it is, objectively, the last defence against human madness. Because
of their actions, men find themselves under an obligation to summon their conscience
in one way or another in both the North and South. The destruction of the planet,
global warming, corruption and new forms of slavery leave them no alternative. We
are now approaching the limits of survival, and ethics now is invested with the power
of the collective consciousness that must teach us how to survive. We are witnessing,
as the philosopher Michel Serres has said, the return of morality. It is no longer the
universality of its principles that allows us to call it ‘the moral law’, as the Kantians
would have it, but the nature of the global catastrophes that threaten the whole planet
and each and every one of us. The return of morality ‘forces’ us to take stock and to
accept that we have an individual responsibility as to how we behave in our day-to-
day lives. A personal ethics obliges us to take another look at our behaviour, our
habits, the amount we consume and our whole way of life. We have come a long way
from philosophical debates and conventional distinctions, and we are witnessing the
marriage or fusion of morality and ethics: we no longer have any real choice between
obligatory universals and individual choices. When we lose our freedom, morality and
ethics are essential.

5 Commentaires

  1. I agree that we should ‘debate and exchange different points of view’ and that ‘the values we share…are not the property of a religion or philosophy that can be imposed on others.’
    I would ask you to consider that slaughter without pre-stunning of the poor animal is unnecessarily more painful and stressful than it could be.
    This is putting one’s own ‘needs’ before the suffering of another creature.
    Consider it from the point of view of the animal.
    As you say ‘The return of morality ‘ forces ‘ us to take stock and to accept that we have an individual responsibility as to how we behave in our day-to-day lives. A personal ethics obliges us to take another look at our behaviour, our habits…’
    Is it ethical to inflict avoidable suffering on an animal, or is it self indulgent?

    • Hi Margaret, are you British? Without any references, it’s difficult to understand what you’re saying or even if you have a grasp on the topic you’re attempting to discuss. I would like the opportunity to know your objective and if you would permit me, I can then answer any questions you have and provide references for you. For now, I can simply inform you that Islam teaches Muslims to protect animals and only kill them under a particular set of circumstances. These circumstances sit within a moral, physical and philosophical framework. In general and put simply, this is how Islamic Jurisprudence works. Therefore, do you have evidence that there are Muslims going against the teachings of Islam? If yes, it might be a relevant topic to take up with a Sharia Court if you have one available to you in your country. If you don’t then perhaps your research shows that Muslim owned abattoirs are less ethical than all other abattoirs of a comparable nature or worst still they are breaking State Law. If yes, then this might be a relevant topic to take up in a State Court, if that’s how this kind of statute is heard in your country. You tell me. If, however, you’re against abattoirs period then I would genuinely like to read your essay on the topic. Please do send me a link. On a side note, perhaps you would also consider joining the if you haven’t already. It’s an issue close to my heart. Another good one is a campaign I read about on this website a while back.

  2. Hi Nisa,
    First of all, thank you very much for replying.
    The RSPCA, a respected animal welfare organisation in Britain, have done extensive research into this topic and the Farm Animal Welfare Council report on the ‘Welfare of Farmed Animals at Slaughter or Killing’ June 2003 concluded
    – The level of restraint of conscious animals required for slaughter without pre-stunning was far greater than for conventional slaughter.
    – A large cut across the neck of a conscious animal would ‘ result in very significant pain and distress ‘ before the animal loses consciousness.
    – ‘ Slaughter without pre-stunning is unacceptable’ and that ‘ the Government should repeal the current exemption.’
    They state that ‘ Evidence clearly indicates that slaughter without pre-stunning can cause unnecessary suffering.’
    The Welfare Council proposed that:
    ‘ UK Jewish and Muslim communities review their slaughter practices.’

    My point is this: should we care about the pain and suffering of animals for slaughter? It is possible to minimise this pain and suffering as a result of technological progress. If religions stick rigidly to ancient religious practices despite this, then I think there is an ethical issue here. Should religious ‘ needs’ be put before the avoidable pain and distress of a sentient creature or is that self indulgent?
    Consider it from the point of view of the animal.

    I’m not sure what you mean by your last three lines, Nisa.Could you clarify? Once again thanks for your response.

  3. Hi Margaret, my apologies, there were several links in the last three lines of my first comment but they’ve disappeared without a trace, leaving those lines illegible. Anyway, thanks for your response. You know, the halal suppliers within the wider UK meat industry aren’t as independent as you might think. But to respond to your issue; I agree it’s self-indulgent to consistently put ones greed before the welfare of animals, especially when there are many other animal-free foods available. I highly doubt the early Muslims consumed meat on a daily basis and regardless of religion and tradition, I believe (like many others) that the global meat and dairy industries are extremely unethical and require far more regulation. Slaughter is just one aspect. I imagine the RSPCA have also conducted studies on the welfare of animals prior to slaughter that show they are in fact better off dead, right? It’s a shame that in the West, we seem to have a lot of sympathy when we hear of animals dying tragically yet we do little to address those who are living tragically. I am very concerned about how animals are killed, but as it’s over pretty quickly no matter which method one uses, it just seems more appropriate to focus on how they live. Other than when I have direct access to a proper halal farm, I practice veganism. Not because I believe we shouldn’t eat meat at all but because Islam instructs mercy and kindness to animals, and there’s nothing halal about factory farming, no matter how many prayers we say. Regarding pre-stunning; has anyone actually told you it’s haram?

    • Hello Nisa,
      Thank you very much for your response.
      I agree totally with your remarks about the welfare and treatment of animals during their lives, but does it have to be an either/or situation with regard to what we focus on? Research shows that slaughter is not ‘over pretty quickly’, particularly without pre-stunning.
      If pre-stunning is not haram, why is it not practised?
      Being ethical oneself is the first step, but nothing changes if we don’t try and bring the plight of animals, during their life and at slaughter, to the attention of everyone, and try and do something about it.

LAISSER UN COMMENTAIRE

S'il vous plaît entrez votre commentaire!
S'il vous plaît entrez votre nom ici